Subject: EPR Approach and Scientific "Explanation"

     To: EdStat-L Statistics Education Discussion List,
         sci.stat.edu Usenet Newsgroup

   From: Donald B. Macnaughton <donmac@matstat.com>
                      (formerly donmac@hookup.net)

   Date: Wednesday July 23, 1997

     cc: Robert Frick <rfrick@psych1.psy.sunysb.edu>

Bob Frick recently wrote to me about the link between the entity-
property-relationship (EPR) approach to statistics and the idea 
of a scientific "explanation".  I am very grateful to Bob for his 
insightful remarks.

Since the issues Bob raises may interest readers of this group 
(and with Bob's permission), following are his remarks together 
with my reply.


1. IS A RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN PROPERTIES A LAW?

Bob starts with two minor issues that set the scene for more im-
portant issues that begin below in section 3.  He writes

>    ( snip )
> I think the goal of science is to collect and test laws and
> theories (with the exceptions that you mentioned).  However,
> the "relationship among properties" sounds like a law.  

I agree.  In 1992 I did a survey of the named "laws" of science 
and found that most of these laws are statements of relationships 
between or among properties of entities.  (I briefly describe the 
survey in appendix A.)

Although I agree that a relationship between properties sounds 
like a law, it seems counter to standard usage to view *all* ac-
cepted relationships between properties as being "laws" of sci-
ence because (as suggested in appendix A) many scientists and 
statisticians restrict their use of the term "law" to only a 
small subset (probably less than 500) of all the hundreds of 
thousands of reliably known relationships between properties.


2. TWO SENSES OF THE WORD "THEORY"

I wrote in an earlier post (1997)

    ... in medical research a scientist might theorize (per-
    haps on the basis of laboratory research) that a particu-
    lar drug has an effect on AIDS.  The implication here of 
    this theory is ...

In response to this passage, Bob writes

> (And, the claim that a drug has a particular effect on AIDS is
> a law, not a theory, to my way of defining things.)

Bob's puzzlement over my use of the word "theory" is due to an 
error on my part in overlooking the fact that the word "theory" 
has more than one meaning.  I wrote thinking of one meaning and 
Bob interpreted the passage thinking of another (more common) 
meaning.  Specifically, if we use the word "theory" to mean a 
"body of interrelated scientific statements", then a statement 
about an untested drug effect is certainly *not* a theory.  On 
the other hand, if we use the word "theory" to mean a hypothesis, 
then a statement about an untested drug effect clearly *is* a 
theory.

I have corrected the text of the essay to remove this source of 
confusion, which I thank Bob for identifying.  In the following 
discussion I shall use the word "theory" only in the sense of a 
body of interrelated scientific statements.


3. WHAT A THEORY?

> So, it seems to me that you overemphasize laws and under-
> emphasize theories.  Of course, that fits with how statistics
> is used.

I view a full-blown scientific theory as being simply a body of 
interrelated statements about
1. the existence of entities
2. the existence of properties of entities (and how to measure 
   them)
3. actual values of properties 
4. distributions of values of properties
5. relationships between entities
6. relationships between properties (relationships between vari-
   ables).

(From the point of view of benefit or payoff, the most important 
statements in a scientific theory are the statements about rela-
tionships between properties because those statements give us the 
ability to predict or control the values of properties -- an 
ability that often has substantial social or commercial value.)

Although I have spent considerable time trying, I have been un-
able to think of much that a scientific theory is beyond the 
above six types of statements.  Can you think of any statements 
in any scientific theory that are not one of the above six types?


On the other hand (as Bob has suggested in a follow-up e-mail), 
not all sets of interrelated statements that are of the above six 
types are scientific theories.  For example, the statements of 
astrology are a set of interrelated statements of (some of) the 
above six types, but these statements do not qualify as a scien-
tific theory.  To qualify as a scientific theory, the statements 
must be derived or verified through *careful empirical research*. 

Thus astrology contains a set of statements of relationships be-
tween properties, namely, relationships between (a) the positions 
of the heavenly bodies at the moment of a person's birth and (b) 
the personality traits of a person.  (E.g., if the sun is in Leo 
when you are born, you will have high leadership ability.)  Since 
there appears to be no concerted movement by astrologers to de-
rive or verify these statements through careful empirical re-
search, astrology does not qualify as a scientific theory.  But 
if these putative relationships between properties ever *are* un-
equivocally verified through careful empirical research, astrol-
ogy *will* then become a valid (though puzzling) scientific the-
ory.

In summary, it is reasonable to view a scientific theory as a set 
of interrelated statements of some or all of the above six types 
that have been derived or verified (or are awaiting intended ver-
ification) through careful empirical research.


4. WHAT IS "EXPLANATION"?

"Explanation" (that is, the ability to "explain") is a highly re-
garded aspect of theories.  Bob suggests a most interesting prob-
lem respecting explanation as follows:

> Consider this.  We know that there is a sun, a moon, and water 
> on the earth.  We know that there is gravity, and we know that
> the tide is highest when the sun and the moon are together, ...
> A nice collection of entities, relationships between entities,
> and relationships between properties.  The remaining problem is
> to explain *why* there are tides.  But to me this is the heart
> of science.

Bob suggests that entities, properties, and relationships are 
nice, but the heart of science is *explanation*.  Implicit in his 
suggestion is the important conjecture that 

    A scientific *explanation* or understanding of some phe-
    nomenon consists of something *beyond* mere identifica-
    tion and linking together of all the relevant entities, 
    properties, and relationships associated with the phe-
    nomenon.

Is this interesting conjecture true?  I devote sections 5 through 
16 below to evaluating the conjecture.  In section 5 I propose a 
proper scientific explanation of why there are tides.  In sec-
tions 6 through 15 I disassemble the explanation into components, 
looking to see what the explanation is made of.  In section 16 I 
summarize the findings.

(Some readers may wonder whether the following discussion has 
much to do with the field of statistics.  The link is that the 
discussion centers around the concept of a relationship between 
variables, and the methods of statistics can all be characterized 
as methods for studying variables and [more importantly] rela-
tionships between variables [Macnaughton 1996].)


5. AN EXPLANATION OF TIDES

Isaac Newton and Pierre Laplace gave us the currently accepted 
explanation of why there are tides (Chandrasekhar 1995, ch. 21).  
To give us something to work with, let me give a simplified ver-
sion of their explanation as follows:

We can "explain" tides in terms of the ethereal and ubiquitous 
type of entity we call a "force".  

(Individual forces are entities in the sense that most people 
linguistically treat them so, by denoting them with a noun [i.e., 
the noun "force"].  Whenever people use a noun, it seems reason-
able to assume that the noun is denoting some "thing", i.e., some 
entity.  Like other entities, forces have properties.  Four im-
portant properties of any force are magnitude, direction, locus 
of application, and type.)


An important type of force that affects tides is the force of 
gravity.  This force simultaneously pulls the water in the oceans 
in three different directions -- toward the earth, toward the 
sun, and toward the moon.  

Consider some particular water molecule in the ocean, which I 
shall call water molecule M.  The magnitude of each of the three 
gravitational forces on this water molecule is given by Newton's 
law of gravitation (a statement of a relationship between proper-
ties of entities),

                               m1 m2
                      f =  G ---------
                             r-squared

where

    f = the magnitude of the force exerted on water molecule M by
        the other body (i.e., by the sun, the moon, or the earth)

   m1 = the mass ("weight") of water molecule M

   m2 = the mass of the other body 

    r = the distance between water molecule M and the center of
        the other body

    G = the gravitational constant, the (empirically determined)
        parameter of the equation.

The direction of the force specified by this equation is away 
from water molecule M and toward the other body along the imagi-
nary line joining the centers of mass of water molecule M and the 
other body.


A second important type of force that affects tides is the cen-
trifugal force, which is a force felt by bodies that are rotat-
ing, and which is directed outward, perpendicular to the axis of 
rotation.  

(Most physicists view centrifugal forces as "imaginary" forces in 
the sense that these forces are only present within a rotating 
frame of reference, and it is often more reasonable to explain 
phenomena in terms of a non-rotating [inertial] frame of refer-
ence.  However, since the current explanation is in the frame of 
reference of an individual [rotating] water molecule, it is ap-
propriate to use centrifugal forces in the explanation.)

The magnitude of the centrifugal force felt by a rotating body is 
given by the relationship between properties

                      f = m omega-squared r

where

    f = the magnitude of the centrifugal force

    m = the mass of the rotating body

omega = the rate of rotation of the rotating body

    r = the perpendicular distance between the rotating body and
        the axis of rotation.

(The above relationship between properties is simply a reworking 
of Newton's second law of motion [f = m a] for the case when the 
acceleration is radial.)

Water molecule M is undergoing three types of rotation
- rotation about the axis of rotation of the earth
- rotation about the center of mass of the earth and moon
- rotation about the center of mass of the earth, moon, and sun.

For any instantaneous configuration of the earth, moon, and sun, 
the centrifugal force felt by water molecule M due to each of the 
above three types of rotation can be computed using the above re-
lationship between properties.  


It is useful to visualize the three gravitational forces and the 
three centrifugal force acting on water molecule M as vectors, 
which are imaginary arrows whose tails are attached to the water 
molecule.  The direction of each arrow indicates the direction of 
the associated force, and the length of each arrow is propor-
tional to the strength of the associated force, as given by the 
above equations.

Using simple vector algebra, we can compute the *vector sum* of 
the six force vectors acting on water molecule M.  The vector sum 
is a single vector pointing in the direction of the *net* force 
on the molecule.  (This vector points almost directly [and occa-
sionally directly] toward the center of the earth, because the 
force of the earth's gravity on water molecule M is several or-
ders of magnitude greater than the next strongest of the five 
other forces.)

If we decompose the net force on water molecule M into two vector 
components, one directed radially toward the center of the earth, 
and the other directed tangentially to the surface of the earth, 
we find that the molecule usually has a small component of force 
on it tangential to the surface of the earth.  This tangential 
force is due to the gravity of the sun and moon and due to the 
three types of rotation.   This force varies in strength and di-
rection over the course of a day, as the positions of the sun and 
the moon change relative to water molecule M.

Every water molecule on the earth experiences the tangential 
forces I describe above, and at any point in time the strength 
and direction of these forces vary in a smooth fashion over the 
surface of the earth.  These tangential forces cause movement of 
the molecules in the direction of the forces.  A noticeable ef-
fect of the movement of the molecules in large bodies of water is 
a lowering of the water level at a shore the water moves away 
from, and a rising of the water level at a shore the water moves 
toward.  The tides are these effects.


I propose that the above paragraphs are a reasonable *high-level* 
scientific "explanation" of why there are tides.  

A lower-level "complete" scientific explanation of why there are 
tides simply embellishes the above explanation with details, 
which may include 
- values of the variables in the two equations to allow computa-
  tion of the actual forces 
- the use of trigonometry (a set of abstract relationships be-
  tween variables that reliably map to the geometry of the real 
  world) to help compute distances and to help with vector addi-
  tion and vector decomposition
- a reworking of the equations in terms of force potential, 
  thereby enabling derivation of a differential equation that can 
  be solved to obtain the equation of the height of the equilib-
  rium surface above or below the nominal height of the ocean un-
  der any configuration of the earth, sun, and moon, as given by 
  Chandrasekhar (1995, sec 115, eq. 15); this equation is another 
  relationship between properties
- equations (stating relationships between properties) that take 
  further account of the fact that the system is not static, and 
  instead the earth, sun, and moon are all in relative motion 
  (Laplace's dynamical theory)
- equations (more relationships between properties) showing the 
  height of the tide at a location as a function of both the 
  water flow rate and the local ocean-floor topography
- other relationships between properties that play (second-order) 
  roles in determining the heights of tides.

Further discussion of tides is given by Pugh (1987) and Marchuk 
and Kagan (1989).


6. DISASSEMBLING THE EXPLANATION OF TIDES

Now that we have a scientific explanation of why there are tides, 
let us disassemble the explanation to see what it is made of.  My 
goal here is to identify *all* the components of the explanation, 
so that we can see whether the explanation goes beyond stating 
and exercising the concepts of entities, properties, and rela-
tionships.  In the following sections I attempt to break out all 
the general ideas that are present in the above explanation of 
tides.


7. EXISTENCE OF ENTITIES

Clearly the explanation of tides relies on the existence of cer-
tain entities.  In particular, the explanation relies on the im-
plied existence of
- the earth
- the oceans on the earth
- the land masses on the earth
- the sun
- the moon 
- the force of gravity
- the centrifugal force
- the tides.

Bob implies the existence of some of these entities quite clearly 
in the second and third sentences in his paragraph above:  "We 
know that there is a sun, ...".  That is, "We know that there ex-
ists a sun, ...".  The exercise of first identifying the main en-
tities in the system we wish to study is an effective way to set 
the scene for subsequent discussion.

(It is reasonable to view the tides as an entity because, as 
noted above, any noun denotes a "thing" that humans treat as an 
entity.  The tides are [or the tide is] an instance of an entity 
that manifests itself [mainly] in terms of changing heights of 
water over the course of a day on the shore of a large body of 
water.  That is, the tides appear as changing values of the prop-
erty "water height".  Note how the human mind likes to make an 
entity out of any "thing" of interest.  In the case of the tides, 
the thing is an instance of the more general type of entity we 
call a "process".  To be meaningful, an entity must have proper-
ties.  An important property of the entity [process] "tide" is 
"water height".)


8. EXISTENCE OF PROPERTIES

In addition to relying on implicit statements about the existence 
of entities, the explanation of tides also relies on implicit 
statements about the existence of various *properties* of the en-
tities, for example
- the explanation relies on two particular properties of the 
  gravitational force:  "magnitude" and "direction"
- the explanation relies on a property of matter:  "mass"
- the explanation relies on the property "distance between two 
  physical objects", which is determined through a coordinate sy-
  stem, as discussed in the next paragraph.


9. COORDINATE SYSTEM

The explanation of tides makes implicit reference to an astro-
nomical coordinate system, which is an imaginary entity that 
helps us to take account of the relative positions of the sun, 
the moon, and the earth.  The coordinates of any body in the co-
ordinate system can be viewed as properties of the body, specify-
ing the body's location in the coordinate system.  Any pair of 
objects in a coordinate system has the property "distance be-
tween", which we need to know for the denominator term in the law 
of gravitation.


10. VALUES OF PROPERTIES

Any detailed explanation of tides must refer to the *values* of 
the properties referenced in the explanation.  For example, if we 
wish to use the law of gravitation to compute the force that the 
sun exerts on water molecule M, we must refer to the actual mass 
of water molecule M and the actual mass of the sun, as well as 
the actual distance between water molecule M and the sun.


11. DISTRIBUTIONS OF VALUES

The explanation of tides refers to the concept of the *distribu-
tion* of the values of a property through the idea of the distri-
bution of the values of the tangential component of the net force 
on molecule M over the course of a day.  

(Statements of distributions are often accorded less importance 
than the other types of statements.  This may be because the 
study of a distribution can be viewed as a degenerate case of the 
study of a relationship between variables.  That is, the study of 
a distribution is the study of the response variable in a rela-
tionship between variables in which the set of predictor vari-
ables is empty.  The use of a non-empty set of predictor vari-
ables is preferred because it gives us a more complete under-
standing of the response variable under study [generally even 
when no relationship is found].)


12. RELATIONSHIPS BETWEEN ENTITIES

The explanation of tides relies on the locational relationships 
between the earth, the sun, and the moon.

(Some examples of possible type of relationships between entities 
X and Y are
- X is a sub-unit or subsystem of Y
- X is a "child" [or other relative] of Y
- X is [in some sense] contiguous with or near to Y.)


13. RELATIONSHIPS BETWEEN PROPERTIES

The explanation of tides relies on many relationships between 
properties.  First, the explanation relies on Newton's law of 
gravitation, which is the relationship between properties that 
allows us to predict the magnitude of a gravitational force.

Second, the explanation relies on Newton's second law of motion, 
which is the relationship between properties that allows us to 
predict the magnitude of a centrifugal force.

Third, the explanation relies on a relationship between proper-
ties reflected in the concepts of vector addition and vector de-
composition of the forces on a body.  I discuss how these con-
cepts reflect a relationship between properties in appendix B.

In addition, the detailed explanation of tides relies on many 
other relationships between properties, as suggested in the list 
at the end of section 5.  


14. LINKING OF CONCEPTS

The explanation of tides relies on a linking together of all the 
concepts discussed in sections 7 through 13.  The linking of con-
cepts in an explanation may be carried out through 
- simple juxtaposition of relevant statements
- the rules of deductive logic or 
- (when mathematical concepts are involved) the rules of mathe-
  matics.

To facilitate studying the linking between the statements, con-
sider the following condensed version of the explanation of 
tides:
(a) There are forces.
(b) There are various forces acting on a water molecule on the 
    earth.
(c) The forces acting on a water molecule can be computed using 
    certain known relationships between properties.
(d) The *net* force acting on a water molecule can be computed 
    from the various individual forces using a certain known re-
    lationship between properties (= vector addition).
(e) The net force acting on a water molecule can be resolved into 
    radial and tangential components using a certain known rela-
    tionship between properties (= vector decomposition).
(f) If the computations in steps (c) through (e) are carried out, 
    we find that the net tangential force on a water molecule on 
    the earth is usually non-zero.
(g) If the net tangential force on a water molecule is non-zero, 
    the molecule will move tangentially, according to Newton's 
    second law of motion (which is a statement of a relationship 
    between properties).
(h) Tides are simply the movement of the water molecules in the 
    oceans caused by the above tangential force components.

Note how statements (c) through (g) center around the concept of 
a relationship between properties of entities.

The actual linkages between statements (a) through (h) are 
- statement (b) is a special set of cases of statement (a)
- statement (c) is an expansion of statement (b) 
- statements (c) through (f) use relationships between properties 
  to derive the conclusion that the net tangential force on a 
  water molecule is usually non-zero
- statement (g) uses a relationship between properties to con-
  clude that the non-zero tangential forces on the water mole-
  cules in the oceans imply that the water molecules will move
- statement (h) states that the tides are the movement described 
  in statement (g).


15. PREDICTION:  THE DEFINITIVE TEST OF AN EXPLANATION

In passing, it is important to note that the definitive test of 
whether the above explanation of tides (or any explanation) is 
valid is not performed on anything internal to the explanation.  
Instead, the test is whether the explanation can accurately 
*predict* the values of the relevant property or variable ("water 
height" in the case of tides) in the future.  That is, scientists 
deem the scientifically "correct" explanation of tides (or any 
other phenomenon) to be the explanation that makes the best pre-
dictions.  

(If I have interpreted the formal scientific work on tides cor-
rectly, most oceanographers and physicists will agree that the 
explanation of tides given above [when embellished with the de-
tails at the end of section 5] makes better predictions of tides 
than any other known explanation of tides.)

Thus note the crucial role that prediction plays in an explana-
tion.  In fact, for some people (including me), the possibility 
of future prediction (or future control) is the actual *goal* of 
any explanation.  That is, people seem to accumulate explanations 
of phenomena in the hope that some of these explanations will 
later be useful in predicting or controlling the values of prop-
erties of entities.


16. SUMMING UP THE ANALYSIS OF THE EXPLANATION OF TIDES

In sections 6 through 14 I analyzed the explanation of tides I 
gave in section 5.  The analysis suggests that a standard scien-
tific explanation of tides contains (sometimes implicitly) the 
following types of statements:
- statements of the existence of entities
- statements of the existence of properties of entities
- statements of the values of properties 
- statements of the distribution of the values of properties 
- statements of relationships between entities
- statements of relationships between properties
- statements linking the other statements together.

Thus it appears that the scientific explanation of tides contains 
the same six types of linked-together statements that I list in 
section 3 as being the six types of statements that make up a 
scientific theory.  

Furthermore, it appears that there is *nothing more* to the sci-
entific explanation of tides beyond the relevant instances and 
linking together of the six types of statements.  

More generally, I suspect that most (all?) scientific explana-
tions can be reasonably viewed as consisting *solely* of relevant 
instances of the six types of statements, and statements that 
link the statements together.  Can you think of any counterexam-
ples?

(Some scientific explanations use another type of statement:  
statements that develop a metaphor.  However, metaphors play only 
an indirect role in explanations, which I discuss in appendix C.)

In section 4 I stated the conjecture that

    A scientific *explanation* or understanding of some phe-
    nomenon consists of something *beyond* mere identifica-
    tion and linking together of all the relevant entities, 
    properties, and relationships associated with the phe-
    nomenon.

The discussion in sections 5 through 16 suggests that the above 
conjecture is false and, instead, the following conjecture is 
true:

    A scientific explanation or understanding of some phe-
    nomenon is simply identification and linking of relevant 
    empirically-studied entities, properties, and relation-
    ships.


17. LINK

I discuss issues about using the entity-property-relationship ap-
proach in an introductory statistics course in material at

                 http://www.matstat.com/teach/

--------------------------------------------------------
Donald B. Macnaughton   MatStat Research Consulting Inc.
donmac@matstat.com      Toronto, Canada
--------------------------------------------------------


APPENDIX A: A CLASSIFICATION OF THE LAWS OF SCIENCE

To investigate how the "laws" of science relate to the concept of 
a relationship between properties, two assistants each carefully 
scanned each page of the 2088-page _McGraw-Hill Dictionary of 
Scientific and Technical Terms_ (Parker 1989) for entries that 
contain the word "law" in the definiendum.  They found 213 en-
tries that define different laws of science.  For each entry I 
then tried to express the definition for the entry in terms of 
the concepts of entities, properties, and relationships.  

I found that three quarters of the laws could be best interpreted 
as statements of relationships between properties of entities 
(relationships between variables).  The remainder of the laws 
fell into seven other categories.  The eight categories (together 
with the number of laws in each category) are shown in the fol-
lowing table:

            Classification of 213 "Laws" of Science 
                Defined in the 1989 _McGraw-Hill
         Dictionary of Scientific and Technical Terms_
   ___________________________________________________________
                                            
                                          Number of
                                           Laws in    Percent
                 Law Category             Category*   of Total
   ___________________________________________________________

        relationship between properties      184         75

      non-relationship between properties     27         11
      (including 10 "conservation" laws)    

              law of mathematics              14          6
              (axiom or theorem)           

         relationship between entities         9          4

              value of a property              5          2

   distribution of the values of a property    4          2

            existence of a property            2          1

            existence of an entity             1         .4

                     other                     0          0
                                            ____       ____

                                  TOTALS     246        100
   ___________________________________________________________

   * The column total is greater than 213 because some laws 
   contained two or more independent statements, each of 
   which was classified separately.    

The first two rows in the body of the table suggest that the ma-
jority of the laws of science are statements about relationships 
between properties of entities (relationships between variables).  

In addition, the classification suggests that many (if not all) 
of the laws of empirical science can be explained in terms of the 
concepts of entities, properties, and relationships.


APPENDIX B: VECTOR OPERATIONS AS RELATIONSHIPS BETWEEN PROPERTIES

In section 13 I noted that the addition and decomposition of vec-
tors can be viewed as reflecting relationships between proper-
ties.  This appendix expands on this point.

Suppose we apply two forces, f1 and f2, to a free body.  Then the 
body will move in a certain direction with a certain amount of 
acceleration.  It is an interesting question whether there is a 
single third force, fe, such that if we apply only fe to the 
body, it will have the same effect on the body as if we had ap-
plied f1 and f2.

This question was addressed empirically by Simon Stevin, Isaac 
Newton, and Pierre Varignon in the late sixteenth and seventeenth 
centuries (Mason 1962, 152).  These researchers applied two 
forces in different directions to a body, and then observed the 
motion of the body.  They then, through a process of trial and 
error, found a single force that would generate the same motion 
of the body.  By examining a large number of cases (using differ-
ent bodies, different sizes of forces, and different directions), 
they found that the specifications of the single force that du-
plicated the action of the two forces could always be obtained 
through a simple rule -- the well-known parallelogram rule of 
vector addition.  

Vector addition of two forces can be symbolized as

                        fe = f1 + f2                          (1)

where fe, f1, and f2 are all force vectors (each encapsulating 
two properties of the associated force:  magnitude and direc-
tion).  The three vectors are defined as

    f1 = magnitude and direction of directed force 1 on the body

    f2 = magnitude and direction of directed force 2 on the body

    fe = magnitude and direction of the effective directed force 
         on the body from f1 and f2.

The plus sign in (1) does not signify standard addition of num-
bers but instead signifies "vector addition" of vectors, as de-
fined by the parallelogram rule.

The terms fe, f1, and f2 in (1) all represent properties or vari-
ables.  (In this case they are a special type of variable, name-
ly, vectors.)  Thus note that (1) is a statement of a relation-
ship between properties (relationship between variables).  A 
natural point of view of (1) is that fe is the response variable 
and f1 and f2 are the predictor variables.

Along with the concept of vector addition, the explanation of 
tides relies on the concept of vector "decomposition" of the net 
force acting on water molecule M into the radial and tangential 
components.  This decomposition is justified through a reversal 
of the operation of vector addition.  This reversal is simply an-
other aspect of the relationship between properties shown in (1), 
and has been shown to be valid through the same empirical re-
search by Stevin, Newton, and Varignon.


APPENDIX C:  THE ROLE OF METAPHOR IN EXPLANATION

A metaphor can offer helpful support to an explanation if there 
is an isomorphism between 
(a) elements (entities, properties, or relationships) in the new 
    system being explained and 
(b) elements (entities, properties, or relationships) in some 
    other familiar system.  
The linking of the two systems through the metaphor helps stu-
dents to understand the new system, because some or all of the 
relationships between elements in the new system can be mentally 
tracked in terms of known relationships between elements in the 
familiar system.  

However, although metaphors are useful memory aids, they gener-
ally do not offer direct logical support for an explanation, be-
cause there is usually no substantive reason (beyond the princi-
ple of parsimony) why the two systems should behave similarly.


REFERENCES

Chandrasekhar, S. (1995), _Newton's Principia for the Common 
   Reader,_ Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Macnaughton, D. B. (1996), "The Introductory Statistics Course:  
   A New Approach."  Available at http://www.matstat.com/teach/

Macnaughton, D. B. (1997), "Response to Comments by John R. 
   Vokey."  Posted to EdStat-L and sci.stat.edu on April 6, 1997 
   under the title "Re: How Should We *Motivate* Students in 
   Intro Stat?"  Available at 
   http://www.matstat.com/teach/p0024.htm

Marchuk, G. I. and Kagan, B. A. (1989), _Dynamics of Ocean 
   Tides._ Translated by V. M. Divid, N. N. Protsenko, and Y. U. 
   Rajabov. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer.

Mason, S. F. (1962), _A Brief History of the Sciences,_ New York: 
   Macmillan.

Parker, S. P., ed. (1989), _McGraw-Hill Dictionary of Scientific 
   and Technical Terms,_ New York: McGraw-Hill.

Pugh, D. T. (1987), _Tides, Surges and Mean Sea-Level,_ Chiches-
   ter, England: John Wiley.

Home Page for the Entity-Property-Relationship Approach to Introductory Statistics